This essay was originally written in graduate school as an assignment for Dr. Christopher Miller’s Conviviality course at Judson University.
In the first chapter of Beauty, Roger Scruton introduces a set of six platitudes (Scruton, Roger. Beauty, (New York: Oxford UP, 2009), 5-6) to help define the subject of beauty and provide a standard to test future theories against. These platitudes, however, create a paradox concerning the judgement of beauty. The first three platitudes are about beauty itself. The fourth platitude introduces the judgement of beauty, which Scruton also refers to as taste. Then, the last two platitudes (five and six) describe the judgement of beauty. It is these last two platitudes that set up the paradox. In platitude five, we learn that when we are describing an object as beautiful, we are describing it and not ourselves. In platitude six however, we learn that there is no way to argue another person into a judgement of beauty that they have not made for themselves. This may not appear contradictory on the surface, but the implications of the sixth platitude cause problems for the fifth. If we accept that there are no “second-hand” judgements of beauty, and that one cannot become an expert in beauty without experiencing and judging beauty for one’s self, then we realize that there must be more to making a judgement about beauty than reason. In fact, according to platitude six, someone must experience beauty for themselves in order to render a legitimate judgment. This means that someone else’s experience of beauty is not enough to inform my own judgment of beauty. But what is the difference between my experience of an object and someone else’s experience of that same object? It is not the object that has changed, it is the subject, or the one having the experience. This creates a problem when we accept the fifth platitude, which clearly states that the judgement of beauty is not a description of the subject’s state of mind. If the description of beauty is purely objective (as the fifth platitude asserts), then it would follow that I need not have my own experience of the beautiful object in order to render a judgement, since my own judgement of the object would in turn be only about that object, and not my state of mind, or experience of it. In this essay, I will argue that the paradox between the fifth and the sixth platitudes can be worked out by accepting the sixth and modifying the fifth to be more accurate about human judgements. In modifying the fifth platitude, I will propose that,
The judgement of taste is about the beautiful object and about the subject’s state of mind. In describing an object as beautiful, I am describing it and me.
Scruton discusses this paradox (Scruton, 7-9) by comparing enjoyment to beauty. He observes that if we haven’t experienced something that others enjoyed, we say that it “seems to be enjoyable” or that it is “apparently enjoyable.” He notices that these judgements focus on the state of the subject’s mind rather than the object. He then distinguishes this from the judgment of beauty. When judging beauty, according to Scruton, we are actually making a statement about the object, we are arguing about an objective reality outside of us which usually involves some sort of rationale. This is very interesting because even though our judgments of beauty are distinct from our judgments of something like enjoyment, they both share the similarity of only being first hand opinions. At this point, Scruton brings this similarity up when he reiterates,
“The judgement of taste is a genuine judgement, one that is supported by reasons. But these reasons can never amount to a deductive argument. If they could do so, then there could be second-hand opinions about beauty. There could be experts on beauty who had never experienced the things they describe, and rules for producing beauty which could be applied by someone who had no aesthetic tastes.” (Scruton, 8)
An important distinction that Scruton makes here is that even though a judgement of taste is supported by reasons, those reasons alone can never amount to a deductive argument that could convince someone who had not first-hand experience. In other words, I can never convince someone that something is beautiful with a reasoned argument. I can only support my own judgement of beauty with reasons. In order to persuade someone else, there is an element that cannot be deduced. Scruton picks this thread up later when talking about being persuaded to like Brahms (Scruton, 136). He concludes that it was not an argument that persuaded him to like Brahms, but a series of internal changes as he listened to the music that allowed Brahms to “work on him” after a while. He also clarifies this point by stating that his change of mind to liking Brahms was not the same kind of “change of mind” as a belief or moral issue. By this, he means that his mind has not been changed by objective means (through argument), rather, his mind has been changed by what he calls “emotional infection” (or through an experience of Brahms again). Shortly after this passage Scruton makes it clear that what he has just argued for is that aesthetic judgement is bound up with the experience of the one who makes it (Scruton, 140). Compare this to the fifth platitude, which states that “In describing an object as beautiful, I am describing it, not me.” (Scruton, 6) These two assertions cannot both be true, because if we accept that the judgement of aesthetics is bound up with the experience of the one who makes it, then we cannot also accept that the judgement only describes the object and not the subject. Of course, the primary purpose of making such a judgement is to describe the object, but in describing the object we are also simultaneously describing something about ourselves. Namely, that there is something about us in particular that derives pleasure from contemplating on this object. In other words, whenever someone describes something as beautiful, they are also describing their own taste. This is because in order to assert that an object is beautiful, a person must be able to experience it as beautiful for them self, which requires their own particular judgement of taste. To say that such a judgment based on experience is only about the object and not about the person is to remove the person from their own experience.
This leads us to reexamine the fifth platitude, since it is actually the only platitude which causes problems for the others. Scruton’s discussion of the “enjoyable” and how it is different from the “beautiful” only led to a reiteration of the paradox because he asserted that the judgement of whether something was enjoyable has to do with the state of the person’s mind and not the object. This is actually only partly the case, because even when someone is emphasizing how they felt while having an experience, they are still telling us about the object of their experience. How could such an experience happen had there not been an object for the subject to experience? But this categorization of the judgement of enjoyment as purely subjective is just what causes the paradox with the judgement of beauty. Scruton assumes that because we emphasize how we feel when we talk about enjoyment, it is a purely subjective judgement. For the same reason, he assumes that because we emphasize a quality about the object when making a judgement of beauty, we are making a purely objective description. But the emphasis of our descriptions do not take away the fact that we are describing an experience, and an experience cannot occur without both a subject and an object. For this reason, the fifth platitude is only partially true. The judgement of taste (not beauty itself) cannot be removed from the subjective realm. Scruton acknowledges this with a reference to Kant (Scruton, 32). Kant says that the judgement of beauty is both universal and subjective. In other words, all humans make judgments about beauty, but these judgements are all based in the experience of beauty, which is necessarily subjective (since we must have both object and subject for an experience to occur).
My case for the modification of the fifth platitude then, is this. If we accept that:
1: The Judgement of Beauty is necessarily based on Experience.
2: Experience requires both a Subject and an Object to occur.
3: The Judgement of Beauty, then, is based on both the Subject and the Object.
4: In describing an Object as Beautiful, I am describing my Experience of it as Beautiful.
5: In describing an Experience of Beauty, I am describing both the Subject and the Object.
Therefore, the fifth platitude may be rendered as:
The judgement of taste is about the beautiful object and about the subject’s state of mind. In describing an object as beautiful, I am describing it and me.
As a clarification, I am not saying that beauty does not reside within the object. I am simply asserting that in order for the judgement of beauty to occur, there must be an experience of beauty first hand. In experiencing the object first hand, there is necessarily both an object and a subject. It follows then that any description of an experience of beauty must describe both the subject’s state of mind and the object.